Aristotle's Concept of The Plot of Tragedy, Its Structure, Its Constituent Elements, Kinds of Plots, and the Concepts of Peripeteia-Anagnorisis
Q.7. The Plot of Tragedy, Its Structure, Its
Constituent Elements, Kinds of Plots, and the Concepts of
Peripeteia-Anagnorisis.
Ans.
In "The Poetics", Aristotle devotes much attention to the examination
of the nature, structure and the formative or constituent elements of an ideal
tragic plot. Tragedy is the representation of action, and action consists of
incidents and events. So, Plot is the arrangement of these incidents and events
in the tragedy. Thus, Plot contains the kernel of the action, which it
is the object of the tragedy. Hence the primary importance of the plot and the
extended and considerable treatment which it receives by Aristotle is very
significant. According to Aristotle, Plot, is the first principle, the soul of
tragedy. So much so Aristotle says that there can be a tragedy without
character and but there can be no tragedy without plot. Out of six
formative elements of a tragedy, i.e., Plot, character, thought, melody,
diction, spectacle-Aristotle assigns the first place to plot. More space has
been devoted to the discussion of the nature, structure, kinds, and the
constituent elements of an ideal plot, than any other of the six formative or
constituent elements of Tragedy.
The Greek word 'poet' means a
'maker'. The poet is a 'maker', not because he makes (writes) verses, but
because he makes plots. Here, Aristotle differentiates between 'story'
and 'plot'. The poet needs not to make his own story; indeed, it would be
better if he chooses a traditional story and then proceeds to make his own plot
out of it. He says that the stories taken from history, mythology, or legend
are to be preferred, for they are familiar and easy to understand, and they
serve as guide-lines for characterisation. After chosen his story or after
inventing it, the dramatist must subject it to a process of artistic selection
and ordering. Only relevant incidents and situations are selected, and they
are arranged in a skilful way that they seem to follow each other necessarily
and inevitably. Moreover, the incidents chosen must be 'serious', of some
importance, and not 'trivial', as tragedy is the imitation of a serious action.
Therefore, the incidents should be 'serious', likely to arouse the
tragic emotions of pity and fear.
Next, Aristotle describe that the
tragic plot must be a complete whole. By 'complete' he means that the
plot must have a proper beginning, middle, and end. It must have a beginning,
i.e., it must not necessarily flow out of some previous situation. There might
be earlier parts of the story, the antecedents, and they may be communicated by
the dramatist in due course of the action. But the beginning must be clear
and intelligible. It must not provoke confusion to ask 'why' and 'how'. It
was the common Greek practice to give the antecedents through the Prologue.
Aristotle says that an effective beginning is the sure test of a dramatist's
skill. The middle is something that is consequent upon a situation that
has gone before, and which is followed by the catastrophe. So the middle is
everything between the first incident and the last. The middle is followed
by the end. 'The end' is that which is consequent upon a given situation, but
which is not followed by any further incident or situation. The middle must
follow naturally and inevitably upon the beginning, and it must logically lead
to the end, or the catastrophe. Thus artistic wholeness implies logical link-up
of the various incidents, events and situations that form the plot.
Then, Aristotle comes to the
important question of Magnitude. The plot must have a certain magnitude.
It must have a certain "length". Here 'Magnitude' means 'size'.
It should be neither too small nor too large. However, it should be long enough
to allow the process of change from prosperity to adversity initiated by 'the
beginning', to be properly and completely developed, but not too long for the
memory to understand it as a whole. Aristotle describes, if it is too long,
the beginning would be forgotten before the end. If it is too small, its
different parts will not be clearly distinguishable from each other, as in the
case of a living organism. Within these limits, the plot should be as large as
possible, however larger the better. Aristotle says that it is the action
itself, not the audience or the judges that should determine the magnitude or
size of the plot. Each drama is a unique problem in poetic craftsmanship,
and what is valid for one may be invalid for another. Aristotle further
describes that Magnitude also implies order and proportion, and as in
the case of a living organism, beauty and order depend upon its magnitude. It's
different parts properly relate to each other and to the whole. Thus magnitude
implies that the plot must have order, logic, symmetry and perspicuity.
Aristotle conceives that the plot
of a tragedy is an organic whole, and also have an organic unity in its
action. An action is a process of change from happiness to misery or vice
versa, and tragedy must depict only one such action. There may be a number of
incidents and events in the play, but together they must constitute one, and
only one, action.. Thus the plot may have variety, but still be a unity and a
whole. This unity arises from the fact that, every event, every incident, has a
logical connection with the rest of the action, and none of them is irrelevant.
There might be episodes indeed, episodes are necessary, for they impart variety
and serve to lengthen out the plot but they must be properly integrated with
the main action. They must be necessary, and they must follow each other
inevitably. Just as every part of the body of a living creature is essential
for its life, and cannot be removed without injury to it, so every incident and
episode must be necessary for the whole. Otherwise, episodic plots are the
worst of all.
Further, Aristotle correlates
organic unity of plot with probability and necessity. The plot deals
with action, incidents and events, which is possible according to the laws of
probability and necessity. So the plot is not tied to what has actually
happened, but it deals with what may probably or necessarily happen under the
given circumstances. Here probability and necessity imply that there should be
no unrelated and unnecessary events and incidents, rather the various events
must be inter-related with a sort of artistic logic. They must follow each
other logically and inevitably and further that nothing should be left to
chance and coincidence or to the 'marvellous', at least in the essential parts
of the action. Thus probability and necessity imply coherence and order and are
essential for artistic unity and wholeness. Moreover, Aristotle says that here
probability implies that the tragic action must be credible or convincing. If
the poet deals with something improbable event, he must have the skill to make
it convincing and credible. He concludes that a convincing impossibility is
preferable to an unconvincing possibility.
The former discussion makes it clear
that Aristotle rules out plurality of action. He emphasises on the Unity
of Action but he has little to say about the Unity of Time and the Unity of
Place. About the Unity of Time he merely says in 'The Poetics "that
tragedy should confine itself, as far as possible, to a single revolution of
the sun. However, no law is implied here. But he has simply made a suggestion,
he has simply pointed out what is desirable. As regards the so-called Unity
of Place, Aristotle only mentioned it once, when he was comparing the epic
and the tragedy, that epic can narrate a number of actions going on
simultaneously in different parts, while in a tragedy only one action can be
represented. On this point again, Aristotle was much misunderstood by
Renaissance critics, and later French critics, that Aristotle was in the
favour of unity of place.
Aristotle says that tragedy is
an imitation of a 'serious action', and that its purpose is to arouse
pity and fear. This means that tragedy is a story of suffering with an
unhappy ending, because it is only such a story that is likely to arouse both
pity and fear. This means, in other words, that the plot of a tragedy must be a
fatal one. Aristotle rules out fortunate plots for tragedy, because such
a plot is not likely to arouse the proper tragic emotions. A tragic plot must
depict the hero passing from prosperity to adversity and not rising from misery
to happiness.
According to Aristotle, Tragic
plots may be of three kinds, (I) Simple, (II) Complex, and (III) Plots based on
or depicting incidents and events of suffering, and depending on their effect.
The words Simple and Complex, have been used here in technical terms. A
Simple plot is one which does not have any Peripety and Anagnorisis, but
the action moves forward uniformly without any violent or sudden change. But
Aristotle prefers Complex plots. An ideal tragic plot, according to Aristotle,
must not be Simple. It must be Complex, i.e., it must have Peripeteia,
i.e., "reversal of intention", and Anagnorisis, i.e.,
"recognition of truth". Peripeteia implies ignorance of truth,
while Anagnorisis is the realisation of truth by some signs, or by chance, or
better still, by the logical development of events. An ideal plot is one in
which Anagnorisis follows or even coincides with Peripeteia, i.e., with the
false step taken by the hero or his well-wishers.
As regards the third kind of
plot, the plot depending for its effect on spectacle-incidents of suffering,
Aristotle rates it very low. It is the plot which derives its effect from the
depiction of spectacle, e.g. torture, murder, maiming, violence, death, etc.
But Aristotle says that tragic effect must be created naturally, and not with
artificial and theatrical aids. Such plots indicate a deficiency in the art of
the poet.
In the end
Aristotle says that in making their plots, the poets should take great care to
make their denouements or 'resolutions', it should be very effective and
successful. While making the denouements, unravelling of the plot should be
done naturally and logically, and not by the use of arbitrary devices, like
chance, supernatural intervention, etc. According to Atkins "Gods
should intervene only where it becomes necessary to explain the past, or
announce future events external to the action". In the same way, Aristotle
does not consider Poetic Justice (ideal justice) as necessary for
Tragedy. He regards it more in keeping with the spirit of comedy. Similarly,
Aristotle rules out the use of plots with a double end, i.e., plots in which
there is happiness for some of the characters, and misery for others. Such a
double-ending plot weakens the tragic effect, and hence must be avoided. It is
more proper to Comedy. Thus Aristotle is against Tragi-comedy.
Points to
Remember:
1.
Introduction.
2.
Plot contains the kernel of action.
3.
Poet means a maker.
4.
Only relevant incidents are selected.
5.
Plot must be a complete whole.
6.
Beginning, Middle and end.
7.
Magnitude.
8.
Probability and necessity.
9.
Aristotle rules out plurality of action.
10.
Peripeteia and Anagnorisis.
11. Conclusion.
*****
Nicd
ReplyDelete