Aristotle’s Concept of Ideal Tragic Hero
Q. Describe Aristotle’s Concept of the Ideal
Tragic Hero.
No passage in the Poetics, with
the exception of the Catharsis phrase, has attracted so great deal of critical
attention as his concept of an ideal tragic hero. The function of a tragedy
is to arouse the emotions of pity and fear in the spectators, and Aristotle
deduces the qualities of his hero from this essential function. An ideal tragic
hero should be good, but not too good or perfect, for the fall of a
perfectly good man from prosperity to adversity, would be odious and repellent
for the spectators. His fall will also not arouse the proper sentiment of pity,
for he is not like us and his undeserved fall would only shock and disgust.
Moreover, his martyrdom is a spiritual victory and the sense of moral triumph
drowns the feeling of pity. The perfectly good man or the saint is
self-effacing and unselfish, so he tends to be passive and inactive. Drama,
on the other hand, requires for its effectiveness a militant and combative
hero. However, in quite recent times, both Bernard Shaw and T.S.
Eliot have achieved outstanding success with saints as their tragic heroes.
Similarly, the spectacle of an utterly wicked person passing from prosperity to
adversity may satisfy our moral sense, but lacks in arousing the proper tragic
sentiments of pity and fear. Because such a person is not like us, and his fall
seems to be well-deserved and in accordance with the requirement of 'justice',
so it excites neither pity nor fear. Thus according to Aristotle, perfectly
good, as well as utterly wicked persons are not at all suitable to be heroes of
tragedies. However, Elizabethan tragedy has demonstrated that even
villains, like Macbeth, can serve as proper tragic heroes and their fall can
arouse the specific tragic emotion of pity. It needs, however, the genius of
Shakespeare to evolve tragic villains of this type. His wickedness is on a
grand level; it is intellectual and resolute, it arises the criminal above the
commonplace and gives to him a sort of dignity. The fall of such a power evokes
a certain tragic feelings in us, or at least a tragic sympathy. It is not the
pity one feels for the unmerited sufferer. But it is a sense of loss and regret
over the waste or misuse of such splendid gifts.
"Provided
a person has some redeeming quality - courage, intellect, beauty, wit,
passionate devotion".
Here again, one might perhaps, offers a
defence of Aristotle, as he has said that completely a depraved person is not
fit to be a tragic hero. One could easily agree that Macbeth was not completely
depraved, for he possessed inordinate courage.
In this connection, it would be
pertinent to remember that Aristotle's conclusions are based on the Greek drama
with which he was familiar, and secondly, that he lays down the qualifications
of an ideal tragic hero, and here he discusses what is the best, not what is
good. On the whole, his views are justified, for it requires the genius of a
Shakespeare to arouse sympathy for an utter villain or a saint.
Having rejected perfection as
well as utter depravity and villainy, Aristotle points out that the ideal
tragic hero,
"must
be an intermediate kind of person, a man not pre-eminently just and virtuous,
whose misfortune, however, is brought upon him not by vice or depravity but by
some error of judgment."
In short, the ideal tragic hero
is a man who stands midway between the two extremes. He is not eminently good
or just, though he inclines to the side of goodness. He is like us, he has so
much of common humanity to arouse our interest and sympathy, but he is an
idealised one. Aristotle says that the tragic hero is not depraved or vicious,
he is also not perfect at the same time, his misfortune is brought upon him by
some fault of his own. In this connection the Greek word used here is "hamartia".
The root meaning of Hamartia is "missing the mark". So the
tragic hero falls not because of some vice or depravity, but because of "miscalculation"
on his part. Hamartia is not a moral failing, but unfortunately it has been
translated rather loosely as, "tragic flaw", by Bradley.
Aristotle himself distinguishes hamartia from moral failing, and makes it quite
clear that he means by it some error of judgment. Butcher, Bywater, and
Rostangi, all these critics agree that 'Hamartia' is not a moral failing;
but an error of judgment which a man commits unconsciously or innocently.
However, Humphrey House tells that Aristotle neither does assert nor
deny anything about the connection of hamartia with moral failings in the hero.
He says: "It may be accompanied by moral imperfection, but it is not in
itself a moral imperfection."
Thus Hamartia is an error of
judgement or miscalculation, it may arise from any of the three ways: First, it
may arise from "ignorance of some material fact or
circumstance", or secondly, it may be an error arising from hasty or
careless view of a given situation, or thirdly, it may be an error
voluntary but not deliberate, as in the case of acts committed in anger or
passion. In "King Lear", Lear commits such an error when he banishes
Cordelia. And in the case of Oedipus all three errors are included. The defect
of Oedipus lies in his proud self-assertion. All serious modern Aristotelian
critics agree that Hamartia is not moral imperfection, though it may be allied
with moral faults, yet it is an error of judgment, whether arising from
ignorance or from some passion. It may even be a character trait, and he may
commit not only one error, but also a series of errors. This conclusion is
borne out by the play Oedipus Tyrannus to which Aristotle refers again and
again, and which may be taken to be his ideal. In this play, the life of the
hero is a chain of errors, the most fatal of all being his marriage with his
mother. The tragic irony lies in the fact that hero may err innocently,
unknowingly, without any evil intention at all, yet his doom is no less than
those who sin consciously. According to Butcher,
"Othello
in the modern drama, Oedipus in the ancient, are the two most conspicuous
examples of ruin wrought by characters, noble indeed, but not without defects,
acting in the dark and, as it seemed, for the best."
Aristotle lays down another
qualification for the tragic hero. He says an ideal tragic hero must be
“enjoyment great reputation and prosperity.” In other words, he must be a
person who occupies a position of lofty eminence in society. He must be
a highly placed and well-reputed individual. This is so because Greek tragedy,
alone with which Aristotle was familiar, was written about a few distinguished
royal families.
But Modern drama has
demonstrated that even a common individual can serve as a tragic hero. They
think that the rank and nobility of birth are now irrelevant. But the common
man, who is selected as the tragic hero, should have uncommon qualities
himself. He should have some sort of dignity so that his fall may arouse the
sense of pity in the spectators.
However, Aristotle's dictum is
quite justified on the principle that, "higher the state, the greater
the fall that follows," or “heavens themselves blaze forth the
death of princes, while the death of a beggar passes unnoticed.” But it
should be remembered that Aristotle nowhere says that the hero should be a king
or at least royal descended, they were the Renaissance critics who distorted
Aristotle and made the qualification more rigid and narrow.
On the whole, we can conclude
that Aristotle's concept of the tragic hero is not unacceptable. Though, in
some ways he had a limited vision. Tragedy is even possible with saints, as
Shaw and Eliot have shown. It is also very much possible with a villainous
character, remarkably shown by the Renaissance dramatists, especially
Shakespeare. However, the chief limitation of Aristotle's concept is that it is
based on only one section of world drama, i.e. Greek drama.
Points to
Remember:
- Introduction.
2. Definition of ideal tragic
hero.
3. Concept of hamartia.
4. Modern drama.
5. Conclusion.
*****
No comments:
Post a Comment